|
Libet Part 1 - The Time Lag
Now, it isn't surprising that there should be some delay
between an event, and our becoming aware of it?
|
This is the kind of stuff people who are targeted end up having to read for years to
understand it all. Trust me, it's not what we want to be doing.
This is essential to understand
The actual important thing to get from this article is simple:
1) If you view the brain from two levels, conscious and unconscious, you discover
that free will is a function of veto power over decisions already made in your
subconscious
2) It typically takes 1/2 sec for your unconscious brain to make a decision to move or
talk or perform any other function. More time to formulate the data to send to the brain
in with a set of instructions on "how to do it". The "data" is then
sent to your conscious, like a micro or a small sub-routine on your computer, at which
time your conscious mind has 1/10th of a second to act or not act upon the command given
by your unconscious
3) This is exactly like the 6 second delay in tv, and I use that example absolutely on
purpose.
4) If it was possible to create a brain to computer interface (which has been done, ask
John
Norseen of Martin Marrietta) and you were able to monitor brain
patterns aka read their mind, there is enough time for that computer to
sense and interpret the brainwave in the unconscious and alter it before it reaches the
conscious, thus effecting mind-control.
All of these things are being done today.
As Norseen says:
If this research pans out, says Norseen, "you can begin to manipulate what
someone is thinking even before they know it." But Norseen says he is
"agnostic" on the moral ramifications, that he's not a mad scientistjust a
dedicated one. "The ethics don't concern me," he says, "but they should
concern someone else."
Norseen predicts profiling by brain print will be in place by
2005
And that's what you need to get from what's below.
|
Libet's short delay
|
2 June 2005
|
|
|
The experiments carried out by Benjamin Libet into the
timing of conscious awareness (briefly described here ) have
provoked, and go on provoking, a vast amount of discussion. His own theory of
consciousness as a kind of field has received somewhat less attention; and the strange
brain-cutting experiment he proposed to test it seems likely to remain unperformed for the
foreseeable future. A large number of papers and discussions have been published: in 2004,
Libet finally summarised his own account in the book 'Mind Time'.
Libet's early research was actually intended to explore
what the minimum stimulus giving rise to a conscious sensation might be. He had an
enviable opportunity to study the response of the brain to direct stimulation (using
trains of electrical pulses) through the help of a friendly neurosurgeon and the
co-operation of a series of patients, who remained conscious and able to report their
sensations throughout the experiment. There are several ways of varying electrical
stimuli, of course, but a curious fact emerged: whatever the voltage or frequency of
the pulses, the stimulus had to persist for about 500 milliseconds before the subject
became consciously aware of it. Actually, this is not quite true: above a certain level of
voltage, the interval decreased, but the current involved was by then well above anything
likely to occur in the brain normally.
The result was unexpected, because it had already
been established that stimuli applied to the skin, rather than directly to the brain,
could be detected consciously even if they were much shorter than 500 milliseconds. Libet
was able to demonstrate that although the stimulus to the skin might be brief, it was
still the case that the resultant brain activity had to persist for 500 milliseconds
before the subject became consciously aware of it. Where a patient was anaesthetised,
the initial brain response to a stimulus was the same as for a fully conscious subject,
but it failed to continue for the required period: moreover, a stimulus applied directly
to the brain 500 milliseconds after one applied to the skin could cancel (or in some
circumstances, enhance) it. |
|
Now, it isn't surprising that there should be
some delay between an event, and our becoming aware of it: indeed, if the normal
process of cause and effect is to be sustained, the event has to precede the
awareness it causes. If we were passive spectators of the world, simply watching
the way we might watch a film, the constant delay would be irrelevant -we should never
notice that we were half a second behind reality. But we also respond to events, and here
a delay is highly relevant and noticeable. The really surprising thing,
therefore, was the length of the delay which seemed to be involved. 500
milliseconds - half a second - is a noticeable period of time, and it is evident that
human beings often respond to events far more quickly than that. If we
had to wait half a second before responding to events, we should never be able to play a
good game of tennis, and we should be dangerous (or extremely cautious) drivers. The answer appeared to be that our unconscious
responses are far quicker than our conscious ones. A stimulus applied to the skin
produces an 'evoked potential' or EP in the brain within tens of
milliseconds, and that seems to be enough for it to register
unconsciously but effectively. A series of experiments have shown that we
register unconsciously a whole host of things which may influence our response to events
but which never cross the threshold into consciousness. Among other evidence, Libet quotes
experiments which show that a conditioned response - a blink - can be created to events
which the subject is never actually conscious of. The remarkable phenomenon of blindsight
might perhaps be seen as a related case. |
|
That still leaves us with a considerable problem. If the
foregoing is true, we ought to be aware of it, surely? On the tennis court we would find
to our surprise that we returned serve competently before we actually saw the ball, and
certainly without thinking about where in the opposite court we might want to put it. Our
conscious and unconscious behaviour would be strangely unsynchronised. Libet's hypothesis
was that conscious awareness is subjectively referred backwards in time. We consciously
perceive the stimulus as occuring at the same moment it registers unconsciously, even
though it doesn't in fact enter our awareness until it has persisted for half a second.
Subjectively we backdate it to match the EP at the beginning rather than the end of the
500 millisecond span. Libet was able to provide
some direct evidence through experiments which, instead of comparing skin stimuli
with direct stimulation of the cortex, instead made a comparison with stimulation of the
medial lemniscus, part of the incoming neural pathway. Each pulse delivered here generates
its own EP, but the sensation is nevertheless referred back to the time of the first in
the train. Backdating remains controversial, however. Perhaps the sensations actually
enter conscious awareness immediately, and the half-second delay merely allows time for
them to become reportable, or fixed in short term memory? Perhaps
we are merely dealing with the difference between being aware of the stimulus, and being
aware that we are aware of it? Libet contends that awareness and memory,
especially declarative, explicit memory, are different and independent phenomena. |
|
There is a further problem to solve, in any
case. The idea of back-reference allows Libet to eliminate the chronological
inconsistencies which threatened to develop in perception, but that leaves our perceptions
at odds with our decision-making. We now seem to perceive the ball before we perceive the
answering stroke of our tennis racquet, but since both seem to occur half a second before
the actual moment of conscious awareness, we should, bizarrely, be seeing
ourselves begin to play the appropriate stroke just before we have consciously decided
which it is. Confronted with this problem, Libet
decided that one more step in the argument was necessary: the perceived time at which we
make a decision must also be subjectively referred back by 500 milliseconds. Unlikely as
it seems, and contrary to our own impression, we must have made our
decisions slightly before we actually become aware of them. |
|
Devising a further experiment to test this hypothesis
was challenging on two counts. First, how can you tell when a decision has been made? In
the case of perception we know when the stimulus occurs, and can track when the initial EP
appears in the brain, but the only symptom of a decision seems to be the resulting action. However, research carried out in 1965
by Kornhuber and Deecke showed that when subjects were asked to move their wrist of
fingers at a moment of their choosing, the act was preceded by a measurable electrical
change in the brain. This 'Readiness Potential' or RP appeared about
800 milliseconds in advance of the act, and seemed to be a clear indication that
the intention to act had formed. It therefore seemed that the RP might be used
experimentally as a marker for the decision.
The second problem lay in how to measure the moment at
which the subject became aware of having made the decision. If the subject had to press a
button or give some other sign, the careful timing would be obscured by the time taken in
doing so - the experiment would be measuring two hand movements and their
associated decisions! Libet's solution was to arrange an oscilloscope so that a bright dot
circled around a kind of clock face every 2.56 seconds (no doubt these days a PC would be
used and the circuit time set to a more rounded figure - but this was 1977). The subjects were simply asked to note the position of the
dot at the moment when they became aware of having decided to move their wrists. This
allowed the timing to be reported accurately while taking the time required for the report
out of the equation.
Of course, the results confirmed the hypothesis: the RP
appeared some 500 milliseconds before the reported awareness of a decision to move. |
|
That sorted out Libet's account in purely empirical
terms: in philosophical terms the problems were only beginning. The research (subsequently
repeated and corroborated by others) seemed to provide a scientific proof
that free will was a delusion. How could we consider ourselves responsible for decisions
we were not even aware of until after they had been made? Some would have been
happy to see the demise of free will, but Libet himself was not ready to let it go so
easily. Although the subject's decision to move occurred too early for it to have been
initiated by conscious thought, there was still - just - a window of
opportunity in which conscious awareness might conceivably veto the move. This window
lasts, on Libet's account, no more than about 100 milliseconds. Experimental proof
is difficult. Libet has conducted experiments in which the subjects were asked to form an
intention to move and then veto it at the last moment: apparently an RP appeared and then
dissipated, but the weirdness of the mental gymnastics required of the subject seem to
leave an element of doubt about the process. Is it possible to
decide to move at a random moment while simultaneously holding on to the belief that you
will not, in fact, execute the movement? Interestingly,
Libet has a moral argument here. He rightly points out that free will is important partly
because it underpins the idea of moral responsibility: but morality, he suggests, is
mainly a matter of vetoing things we have a built-in tendency to do. This is a faintly
depressing prospect, and I think Libet underestimates the difficulty of discriminating
between doing and not-doing. If I veto my momentary desire to kill you, that surely is
morally good: but what if I repress the automatic tendency to grab your hand when you are
about to fall off the cliff? |
|
There are several avenues of attack against Libet's
other conclusions, of course. Is the RP really a signal that a decision has been
made? If I make a decision about my insurance policy, does an RP appear, or is
it just wrist movements that cause RPs? The circumstances of both Libet's
experiments and the earlier ones by Kornhuber and Deecke are rather strange: they
require the subject to get into a frame of mind where they are ready to make a decision
any moment. Might not the RP merely signal a quickening of attention, rather than a moment
of decision? Libet believes that by timing
the moment of awareness through his oscilloscope arrangement, he eliminated the
need for the subject to spend any time on reporting the moment of awareness: but
isn't it possible that we need a certain amount of time just in order to report
the awareness to ourselves? Awareness of the decision you have made is one
thing, being aware of that awareness is another - which might well be thought to
require some further time to develop.
Personally I also doubt whether it is necessary to reduce
free will to a veto system - 'free won't' as it has
been described. Libet often seems to take it for granted that every free act is preceded
by a specific act of will: but that isn't really the case. Often the conscious mind sets a
general plan, on which we then act more or less automatically. A tennis player
has thought in general terms about how to play the next stroke long before the need for
actual action: drivers have a kind of running rule in the back of their mind to the
effect that if something suddenly appears in front of them, they hit the brake. Free will
operates at this higher level, with all our actions being managed in detail by unconscious
processes. I don't have to think about where I want to hit the ball at the very
moment of decision in order to control my game of tennis any more than I have to think
separately about each of the individual muscles I am implicitly proposing to contract. |
|
Libet has another string to his bow, however, inasmuch
as his general theory of consciousness is also designed to offer a foothold for free
will, along with the subjective experience which in his view sustains it: free decisions
are conscious decisions, and conscious decisions require subjective awareness. He
proposes a conscious mental field (CMF) intended to account for the various mental
phenomena which don't appear to be natural consequences of the firing of neurons. Like
other proponents of field theories, Libet believes that the prescence of such a field
helps explain how the diverse activity of the brain is bound together into a single,
unified conscious experience. Unlike Susan Pockett or Johnjoe McFadden , however, he
does not see this field as a straightforward physical phenomenon. Libet, who says that
when young he was convinced of the truth of determinist materialism, no longer believes
that conscious mental activity is explainable by or reducible to, neuronal activity,
although it certainly requires it. He is not, at the same time, advocating any kind of
dualism or spiritual theory: instead (and rather obscurely, I think) it seems that
his proposed CMF is an emergent phenomenon: something that arises from the combination of
active neurons but amounts to something distinctively more than, and different from, the
sum of brain activity. |
|
In order to verify the theory, Libet
has proposed a rather alarming experiment. If a small slab of living brain in a
suitable area of the cortex, could be cut off from its neural connections while being left
with a suitable blood supply, he believes it would remain capable of producing subjective
experience, mediated by the CMF, when appropriately stimulated. (Actually the slab
would have to have some minimal neural input to keep it 'awake', but this could apparently
be managed without spoiling the experiment.) The existence and role of the CMF
would thereby be demonstrated - though I imagine there would still be considerable
resistance to the idea and a host of objections to the experiment. The immediate theoretical objection which springs to mind is to
ask why the brain goes to such trouble to make neural connections if it can do its
normal job without them: Libet's answer is that it can't do the 'normal jobs' of
information processing, memory, emotional response and all the rest: it's just the
subjective aspect which arises from the CMF.
Of course, there are also practical difficulties: you
cannot cut out slabs of living human brain purely for experimental purposes. Libet has
identified a method and a category of patients in whom the experiment could theoretically
be performed innocuously, namely those who are already going to have an epileptic focus
surgically removed. Very few patients of this kind exist, and Libet has had no success in
interesting the surgeons in these cases in facilitating his experiment. |
|